Results for 'Ralph Clarence Kennedy'

996 found
Order:
  1. The social brain in psychiatric and neurological disorders.Daniel P. Kennedy & Ralph Adolphs - 2012 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 16 (11):559-572.
    Psychiatric and neurological disorders have historically provided key insights into the structure-function rela- tionships that subserve human social cognition and behavior, informing the concept of the ‘social brain’. In this review, we take stock of the current status of this concept, retaining a focus on disorders that impact social behavior. We discuss how the social brain, social cognition, and social behavior are interdependent, and emphasize the important role of development and com- pensation. We suggest that the social brain, and its (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  2.  13
    Conditioning imagery.Clarence Leuba & Ralph Dunlap - 1951 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 41 (5):352.
  3.  12
    Rational Belief Systems.Ralph Kennedy - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (3):668-670.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  4.  72
    The dutch book argument: Its logical flaws, its subjective sources.Ralph Kennedy & Charles Chihara - 1979 - Philosophical Studies 36 (1):19 - 33.
  5. Extreme self-denial.Ralph C. Kennedy & George Graham - 2007 - In M. Marraffa, M. Caro & F. Ferretti (eds.), Cartographies of the Mind: Philosophy and Psychology in Intersection. Springer.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6.  41
    An improvement on Zabludowski's critique of Goodman's theory of projection.Ralph Kennedy & Charles Chihara - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (5):137-141.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Salmon versus Kripke on the A Priori.Ralph Kennedy - 1987 - Analysis 47 (3):158 - 161.
  8.  51
    Lemmon on Logical Relations.Ralph Kennedy - 1985 - Analysis 45 (2):89 - 93.
  9.  11
    Beyond zabludowskian competitors: A new theory of projectibility.Ralph Kennedy & Charles Chihara - 1978 - Philosophical Studies 33 (3):229 - 253.
  10.  50
    How not to derive 'is' from 'could be': Professor William Rowe on the ontological argument.Ralph Kennedy - 1989 - Philosophical Studies 55 (3):293 - 302.
  11.  22
    On the projection of novel predicates.Ralph C. Kennedy - 1977 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 15 (4):487-492.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  12
    On the Projection of Novel Predicates.Ralph C. Kennedy - 1977 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 15 (4):487-492.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  11
    Professor Aune on epistemic justification.Ralph Kennedy - 1981 - Philosophical Studies 40 (3):431 - 437.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  98
    Professor Chisholm and the Problem of the Speckled Hen.Ralph Kennedy - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Research 18:143-147.
    The Problem of the Speckled Hen is a potential stumbling-block for any philosophical treatment of perceptual certainty. Roderick Chisholm argues in the third edition of his Theory of Knowledge (Prentice Hall, 1989) that the Speckled Hen is not a problem for the account of the perceptually certain contained in that book. In this note, I argue that Chisholm’s defense of his account does not work.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  39
    The principle of wanton embedding.Ralph Kennedy & Charles Chihara - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74 (9):539-540.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  15
    Thomas K. Hearn Jr., 1937-2008.Gregory Pence, Ralph Kennedy, George Graham & Alan Fuchs - 2008 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 82 (2):161 - 162.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  14
    Brian Ellis. Rational belief systems. APQ library of philosophy. Rowman and Littlefield, Totowa, N.J., 1979, ix + 118 pp. [REVIEW]Ralph Kennedy - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (3):668-670.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. "The Identity of the Self" by Geoffrey Madell. [REVIEW]Ralph Kennedy - 1985 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 (3):467.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  36
    Ralph Hanna and David Lawton, eds., The Siege of Jerusalem. (Early English Text Society, O.S., 320.) Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, for the Early English Text Society, 2003. Pp. xcix, 224 plus black-and-white frontispiece; black-and-white figures and tables.Ruth Kennedy, ed., Three Alliterative Saints' Hymns: Late Middle English Stanzaic Poems. The Alliterative Katherine Hymn by Richard Spalding (Bodleian Library MS Bodley Rolls 22); the Alliterative John Evangelist Hymn (Lincoln Cathedral Library MS 91); the Alliterative John Baptist Hymn (British Library Additional MS 39574). (Early English Text Society, O.S., 321.) Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, for the Early English Text Society, 2003. Pp. cix, 120 plus black-and-white frontispiece and black-and-white figures; tables. [REVIEW]Ad Putter - 2006 - Speculum 81 (2):524-526.
  20.  4
    Decisions with Multiple Objectives.Ralph Keeney & Howard Raiffa - 1976 - New York: Wiley.
  21. Investigating Emotions as Functional States Distinct From Feelings.Ralph Adolphs & Daniel Andler - 2018 - Emotion Review 10 (3):191-201.
    We defend a functionalist approach to emotion that begins by focusing on emotions as central states with causal connections to behavior and to other cognitive states. The approach brackets the conscious experience of emotion, lists plausible features that emotions exhibit, and argues that alternative schemes are unpromising candidates. We conclude with the benefits of our approach: one can study emotions in animals; one can look in the brain for the implementation of specific features; and one ends up with an architecture (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  22. Conceptual role semantics for moral terms.Ralph Wedgwood - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (1):1-30.
    This paper outlines a new approach to the task of giving an account of the meaning of moral statements: a sort of "conceptual role semantics", according to which the meaning of moral terms is given by their role in practical reasoning. This role is sufficient both to distinguish the meaning of any moral term from that of other terms, and to determine the property or relation (if any) that the term stands for. The paper ends by suggesting reasons for regarding (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  23. Defending double effect.Ralph Wedgwood - 2011 - Ratio 24 (4):384-401.
    This essay defends a version of the Doctrine of Double Effect (DDE) – the doctrine that there is normally a stronger reason against an act that has a bad state of affairs as one of its intended effects than against an otherwise similar act that has that bad state of affairs as an unintended effect. First, a precise account of this version of the DDE is given. Secondly, some suggestions are made about why we should believe the DDE, and about (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  24. Doxastic Correctness.Ralph Wedgwood - 2013 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 87 (1):217-234.
    If beliefs are subject to a basic norm of correctness—roughly, to the principle that a belief is correct only if the proposition believed is true—how can this norm guide believers in forming their beliefs? Answer: this norm guides believers indirectly: believers are directly guided by requirements of rationality—which are themselves explained by this norm of correctness. The fundamental connection between rationality and correctness is probabilistic. Incorrectness comes in degrees; for beliefs, these degrees of incorrectness are measured by quadratic scoring rules, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  25. Racial capitalism.Michael Ralph & Maya Singhal - 2019 - Theory and Society 48 (6):851-881.
    “Racial capitalism” has surfaced during the past few decades in projects that highlight the production of difference in tandem with the production of capital—usually through violence. Scholars in this tradition typically draw their inspiration—and framework—from Cedric Robinson’s influential 1983 text, Black Marxism: The Making of the Black Radical Tradition. This article uses the work of Orlando Patterson to highlight some limits of “racial capitalism” as a theoretical project. First, the “racial capitalism” literature rarely clarifies what scholars mean by “race” or (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26. The Right Thing to Believe.Ralph Wedgwood - 2013 - In Timothy Chan (ed.), The Aim of Belief. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 123-139.
    Many philosophers have claimed that “belief aims at the truth”. But is there any interpretation of this claim on which it counts as true? According to some philosophers, the best interpretation of the claim takes it as the normative thesis that belief is subject to a truth-norm. The goal of this essay is to clarify this normative interpretation of the claim. First, the claim can be developed so that it applies to partial beliefs as well as to flat-out full beliefs. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  27.  39
    Newton on Matter and Activity.Ralph C. S. Walker & Ernan McMullin - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (120):249.
  28. Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly.Ralph Wedgwood - 2003 - In Sarah Stroud & Christine Tappolet (eds.), Weakness of will and practical irrationality. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 201--229.
    Let us take an example that Bernard Williams (1981: 102) made famous. Suppose that you want a gin and tonic, and you believe that the stuff in front of you is gin. In fact, however, the stuff is not gin but petrol. So if you drink the stuff (even mixed with tonic), it will be decidedly unpleasant, to say the least. Should you choose to drink the stuff or not?
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  29. The "Good" and the "Right" Revisited.Ralph Wedgwood - 2009 - Philosophical Perspectives 23 (1):499-519..
    Moral philosophy has long been preoccupied by a supposed dichotomy between the "good" and the "right". This dichotomy has been taken to define certain allegedly central issues for ethics. How are the good and the right related to each other? For example, is one of the two "prior" to the other? If so, is the good prior to the right, or is the right prior to the good?
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  30. Author Reply: We Don’t Yet Know What Emotions Are.Ralph Adolphs & Daniel Andler - 2018 - Emotion Review 10 (3):233-236.
    Our approach to emotion emphasized three key ingredients. We do not yet have a mature science of emotion, or even a consensus view—in this respect we are more hesitant than Sander, Grandjean, and Scherer or Luiz Pessoa. Relatedly, a science of emotion needs to be highly interdisciplinary, including ecology, psychology, neuroscience, and philosophy. We recommend a functionalist view that brackets conscious experiences and that essentially treats emotions as latent variables inferred from a number of measures. But our version of functionalism (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31. The a priori rules of rationality.Ralph Wedgwood - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (1):113-131.
    Both these ideas are intuitively plausible: rationality has an external aim, such as forming a true belief or good decision; and the rationality of a belief or decision is determined purely by facts about the thinker’s internal mental states. Unlike earlier conceptions, the conception of rationality presented here explains why these ideas are both true. Rational beliefs and decisions, it is argued, are those that are formed through the thinker’s following ‘rules of rationality’. Some rules count as rules of rationality (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  32. Contextualism about justified belief.Ralph Wedgwood - 2008 - Philosophers' Imprint 8:1-20.
    This paper presents a new argument for a form of contextualism about ‘justified belief’, the argument being based on considerations concerning the nature of belief. It is then argued that this form of contextualism, although it is true, cannot help to answer the threat of scepticism. However, it can explain many other puzzling phenomena: it can give an account of the linguistic mechanisms that determine how the extension of ‘justified belief’ shifts with context; it can help to defuse some puzzles (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  33.  23
    A field ion microscope study of some tungsten-rhenium alloys.Brian Ralph & D. G. Brandon - 1963 - Philosophical Magazine 8 (90):919-934.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  34. Sensing values?Ralph Wedgwood - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (1):215-223.
    This is a reply to Mark Johnston's paper "The Authority of Affect", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (2001).
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  35.  18
    Why Do SMEs Go Green? An Analysis of Wine Firms in South Africa.Ralph Hamann, James Smith, Pete Tashman & R. Scott Marshall - 2017 - Business and Society 56 (1):23-56.
    Studies on why small and medium enterprises engage in pro-environmental behavior suggest that managers’ environmental responsibility plays a relatively greater role than competitiveness and legitimacy-seeking. These categories of drivers are mostly considered independent of each other. Using survey data and comparative case studies of wine firms in South Africa, this study finds that managers’ environmental responsibility is indeed the key driver in a context where state regulation hardly plays any role in regulating dispersed, rural firms. However, especially proactive firms are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36. The price of non-reductive moral realism.Ralph Wedgwood - 1999 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2 (3):199-215.
    Non-reductive moral realism is the view that there are moral properties which cannot be reduced to natural properties. If moral properties exist, it is plausible that they strongly supervene on non-moral properties- more specifically, on mental, social, and biological properties. There may also be good reasons for thinking that moral properties are irreducible. However, strong supervenience and irreducibility seem incompatible. Strong supervenience entails that there is an enormous number of modal truths (specifically, truths about exactly which non-moral properties necessitate which (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  37.  64
    Using and Abusing Nietzsche for Environmental Ethics.Ralph R. Acampora - 1994 - Environmental Ethics 16 (2):187-194.
    Max Hallman has put forward an interpretation of Nietzsche’s philosophy according to which Nietzsche is a prototypical deep ecologist. In reply, I dispute Hallman’s main interpretive claim as well as its ethical and exegetical corollaries. I hold that Nietzsche is not a “biospheric egalitarian,” but rather an aristocratically individualistic “high humanist.” A consistently naturalistic transcendentalist, Nietzsche does submit a critique of modernity’s Christian-inflected anthropocentrism (pace Hallman), and yet—in his later work—he endorses exploitation in the quest for nobility (contra Hallman). I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  38.  30
    More on Regular Reduced Products.Juliette Cara Kennedy & Saharon Shelah - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (4):1261 - 1266.
    The authors show. by means of a finitary version $\square_{\lambda D}^{fin}$ of the combinatorial principle $\square_\lambda^{h*}$ of [7]. the consistency of the failure, relative to the consistency of supercompact cardinals, of the following: for all regular filters D on a cardinal A. if Mi and Ni are elementarily equivalent models of a language of size $\leq \lambda$ , then the second player has a winning strategy in the Ehrenfeucht- $Fra\uml{i}ss\acute{e}$ game of length $\lambda^{+}$ on $\pi_{i} M_{i}/D$ and $\pi_{i} N_{i}/D$ . (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39.  91
    The Price of Non‐Reductive Physicalism.Ralph Wedgwood - 2000 - Noûs 34 (3):400-421.
    Nonreductive physicalism faces a serious objection: physicalism entails the existence of an enormous number of modal facts--specifically, facts about exactly which physical properties necessitate each mental property; and, it seems, if mental properties are irreducible, these modal facts cannot all be satisfactorily explained. The only answer to this objection is to claim that the explanations of these modal facts are themselves contingent. This claim requires rejecting "S5" as the appropriate logic for metaphysical modality. Finally, it is argued that rejecting "S5" (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  40.  95
    “How to Compare?” - On the Methodological State of Comparative Philosophy.Ralph Weber - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (7):593-603.
    From early on, comparative philosophy has had on offer a high variety of goals, approaches and methodologies. Such high variety is still today a trademark of the discipline, and it is not uncommon of representatives of one camp in comparative philosophy to think of those in other camps as not really being about ‘comparative philosophy’. Much of the disagreement arguably has to do with methodological problems related to the concept of comparison and with the widely prevailing but unwarranted assumption that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  41. Practical reasoning as figuring out what is best: Against constructivism.Ralph Wedgwood - 2002 - Topoi 21 (1-2):139-152.
  42. Theories of content and theories of motivation.Ralph Wedgwood - 1995 - European Journal of Philosophy 3 (3):273-288.
    According to the anti-Humean theory of motivation, it is possible to be motivated to act by reason alone. According to the Humean theory of motivation, this is impossible. The debate between these two theories remains as vigorous as ever (see for example Pettit 1987, Lewis 1988, Price 1989 and Smith 1994). In this paper I shall argue that the anti-Humean theory of motivation is incompatible with a number of prominent recent theories of content. I shall focus on causal or informational (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43.  17
    Non-strictly positive fixed points for classical natural deduction.Ralph Matthes - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 133 (1):205-230.
    Termination for classical natural deduction is difficult in the presence of commuting/permutative conversions for disjunction. An approach based on reducibility candidates is presented that uses non-strictly positive inductive definitions.It covers second-order universal quantification and also the extension of the logic with fixed points of non-strictly positive operators, which appears to be a new result.Finally, the relation to Parigot’s strictly positive inductive definition of his set of reducibility candidates and to his notion of generalized reducibility candidates is explained.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44.  68
    Why Talk about Chinese Metaphysics?Ralph Weber - 2013 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 8 (1):99-119.
  45. General Logic.Ralph M. Eaton - 1932 - The Monist 42:155.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  46. General Logic.Ralph M. Eaton - 1932 - Philosophy 7 (26):235-239.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47. Philosophy schools across Australia.Liz Fynes-Clinton Kate Kennedy White, Jill Howells Lynne Hinton, Daniel Smith Emmanuel Skoutas & Matthew Wills - 2019 - In Gilbert Burgh & Simone Thornton (eds.), Philosophical Inquiry with Children: The development of an inquiring society in Australia. Abingdon, UK: Routledge.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  62
    Intrinsic values and reasons for action.Ralph Wedgwood - 2009 - In Ernest Sosa & Enrique Villanueva (eds.), Metaethics. Boston: Wiley Periodicals. pp. 321-342.
    What reasons for action do we have? What explains why we have these reasons? In this paper, I shall articulate some of the basic structural features of a theory that would provide answers to these questions. So my primary focus here is on the nature of reasons for action themselves, not on the meaning of the terms that can be used to talk about such reasons. However, it seems plausible that the term "reason for action" is in fact used in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49. Induction and Transcendental Argument.Ralph Cs Walker - 1999 - In Robert Stern (ed.), Transcendental Arguments: Problems and Prospects. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  50.  18
    Quine en Perspective.Ralph C. S. Walker & Paul Gochet - 1978 - Philosophical Quarterly 28 (113):357.
1 — 50 / 996